The Stone Lyceum presentation on happiness went well. The two Methodist University faculty members who responded to my talk were both thoughtful in their responses, and the three presentations together generated a good deal of interesting discussion. Lynda Brey, who was sitting in the front row, took a picture of me giving the talk. Here it is:
The two responders both were kind enough to send me copies of their remarks, and I’ll post each of them. The comments below are from Michael Potts, a professor of philosophy. He does a good job of explaining the dangers of pursuing happiness isolated from any concern about virtue or ethics. His beginning example is especially powerful.
Response to Robert Ritzema, “Happiness: Let’s Stop Pursuing It”
Although contemporary psychologists are loath to admit it, their subjective view of happiness amounts to the notion that happiness is the same thing as pleasurable states, or at least a life in which pleasurable states outnumber painful ones. Tonight I want to tell you the story of Theodore, a subjectively happy man. He enjoyed a number of pleasurable feelings throughout his life and felt himself to be happy. In high school he was vice-president of the Methodist Youth Fellowship at his local church and was also a boy scout. Later, he was politically active, attending the 1968 Republican National Convention in Miami Beach as a supporter of then New York governor Nelson Rockefeller. He eventually attended law school. But these activities ultimately did not provide him the level of subjective satisfaction he desired. Later on, when he changed his life in a way he believed would make him happy, it worked–he became more satisfied with his life, and hoped to continue in the course of life he had chosen.
One evening Theodore was having a nice, quiet philosophical discussion with a young woman. After arguing that all moral judgments are subjective, and each person has the right to follow his or her own morality, Theodore argued that being free to do what he wanted to do made him happy. He stated that his view implied that human beings have no more rights than those of other animals. He asked the woman:
Why is it more wrong to kill a human animal than any other animal, a pig, a sheep, or a steer? ….Why should I be willing to sacrifice my pleasure more for the one than for the other? Surely you would not, in this age of scientific enlightenment, declare that God or nature has marked some pleasures as “moral” or “good” and others as “immoral” or “bad”? In any case, let me assure you, my dear young lady, that there is absolutely no comparison between the pleasure I might take in eating ham and the pleasure I anticipate in raping and murdering you.1
Here ends the statement of Theodore Robert Bundy, commonly known as Ted Bundy, just before he killed one of his thirty (perhaps as many as one-hundred) victims. Ted Bundy was a happy serial killer. If he had not been caught and eventually executed, he might be busy pursing happiness today.
The Ted Bundy example reveals one of two major problems with the phrase, “pursuing happiness.” Not all “happinesses” are equal. Exactly what are we supposed to be pursuing? If “happiness” is only subjective, then it has to be identified with some kind of pleasurable state or series of states. Yet on that conception, Ted Bundy or Joseph Mengele, the brutal Nazi doctor who tortured Jewish concentration camp prisoners in brutal medical experiments, could be considered “happy.” Mengele lived comfortably in Argentina until he died as an old man in a swimming accident. Suppose he did not regret his medical experiments and felt himself to be happy. Suppose one reason he felt happy is that he believed he was doing good with his medical experiments. Could we then praise him for “pursuing happiness”?
But as Professor Ritzema has wisely noted, there is an alternative conception of “happiness” that was common in the ancient and medieval worlds and most closely associated with Aristotle. Aristotle referred to happiness by the Greek word εύδαιμονία, which is best translated as “enlightened well-being.” He sharply attacks the notion that happiness is pleasure, saying that this view is accepted by “the most vulgar,” and that a life based only on pursuing pleasure is “completely slavish…a life for grazing animals.”2
Now for those of us who would rather not live like cows or hogs, a higher conception of happiness than pleasure is required: eudaimonia, which Aristotle defines as an activity of the soul in accord with virtue. Virtues are stable character traits which we develop through habituation, such as courage, justice, and in Christian thought, charity. These virtues help us to become truly human, to fulfill our human nature to the highest degree, to be, as the old Army ads used to say, “all that we can be.” Virtues are also oriented toward the good of a human community and not only toward the good of the individual—they encompass both. On this account, happiness must include practical action for the good of those people with whom we interact, including family members, friends, neighbors, and the wider world.
Happiness is, therefore, not merely a subjective term—it involves much more than our personal pleasure. This does not imply that pleasure cannot be part of happiness—Aristotle believes, for example, that if we are truly virtuous we will enjoy doing the things that are good. He also believes that one cannot be happy if painful external circumstances, such as chronic illness or severe poverty permeate a person’s life. But it does imply that a bad person cannot be truly happy, no matter how much pleasure the person may experience in life and no matter how satisfied the person may feel with life.
Traditional Christianity goes even further than Aristotle. In the Sermon on the Mount, Jesus says, “Blessed are those who mourn,” “Blessed are those who are persecuted for righteousness’ sake,” and “Blessed are you when men revile you and persecute you and utter all kinds of evil against you falsely for my sake.”3 Unless we are to presume that the early Christians were masochists, we can assume that when they were eaten by lions and burned to death that these were painful experiences. How can they be “blessed,” (a word which can also be translated as “happy”) while suffering? They can be happy, according to Christianity, because happiness, or blessedness, is not a subjective matter, but a matter of following one’s true and ultimate goal, that is, God. A life of following God is a blessed or happy life even if subjectively it contains many more painful experiences than pleasant ones.
This serves as a corrective of the modern view that happiness consists of subjective pleasurable states. If we strive to live a blessed life that is something that can be accomplished whether or not we have good or bad fortune, or whether or not we feel subjectively happy. If we strive for pleasurable states, that is usually the best way not to have pleasant states—this is the so-called paradox of hedonism. It is usually when we’re not consciously trying to experience pleasure that we actually experience pleasure. So even if happiness is pleasure, we must seek something other than pleasure in order to attain such happiness. But this implies that true happiness is not something that is merely subjective; happiness involves going outside ourselves—whether that is loving your family and friends, or loving God. The important thing is that what you focus on in life be a worthy goal—and then you work to develop the virtues necessary to attain that goal. Not everyone is religious in the same way, so not everyone will agree that loving God is part of a blessed or happy life. But surely all people can agree that a person who has virtues such as charity, integrity, courage, justice, temperance—all virtues that help people get along in a world too often filled with strife—that person is truly happy.
NOTES
1Statement by Ted Bundy, paraphrased and rewritten by Harry V. Jaffa, Homosexuality and the Natural Law (Claremont, CA: Claremont Institute for the Study of Statesmanship and Political Philosophy, 1990, 3-4), as quoted in Louis J. Pojman, Ethics: Discovering Right and Wrong, 5th ed. (Belmont, CA: Thompson/Wadsworth, 2006), 30.
2Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin, 2nd ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1999), I, 5, 1095b18-21.
3Matthew 5:4, 10, 11. From The Holy Bible, Revised Standard Version, second edition (National Council of Christian Churches in the United States of America, 1971).